What is it about?

Demonstrative logic is the study of demonstration as opposed to persuasion. It is the subject of Aristotle’s two-volume Analytics, as he said in the first sentence. Many of his examples are geometrical. Every demonstration produces (or confirms) knowledge of (the truth of) its conclusion for every person who comprehends the demonstration. Persuasion merely produces opinion. Aristotle presented a general truth-and-consequence conception of demonstration meant to apply to all demonstrations. According to him, a demonstration is an extended argumentation that begins with premises known to be truths and that involves a chain of reasoning showing by deductively evident steps that its conclusion is a consequence of its premises. In short, a demonstration is a deduction whose premises are known to be true. Aristotle’s general theory of demonstration required a prior general theory of deduction presented in the Prior Analytics. His general immediate-deduction-chaining conception of deduction was meant to apply to all deductions. According to him, any deduction that is not immediately evident is an extended argumentation that involves a chaining of immediately evident steps that shows its final conclusion to follow logically from its premises.

Featured Image

Why is it important?

This expository paper on Aristotle’s demonstrative logic is intended for a broad audience that includes non-specialists. Demonstrative logic is the study of demonstration as opposed to persuasion. It presupposes the Socratic knowledge/belief distinction – between knowledge (beliefs that are known) and opinion (those that are not known). Demonstrative logic is the subject of Aristotle’s two-volume Analytics, as he said in the first sentence. Many of his examples are geometrical. Every demonstration produces (or confirms) knowledge of (the truth of) its conclusion for every person who comprehends the demonstration. Persuasion merely produces opinion. Aristotle presented a general truth-and-consequence conception of demonstration meant to apply to all demonstrations. According to him, a demonstration is an extended argumentation that begins with premises known to be truths and that involves a chain of reasoning showing by deductively evident steps that its conclusion is a consequence of its premises. In short, a demonstration is a deduction whose premises are known to be true. For Aristotle, starting with premises known to be true, the knower demonstrates a conclusion by deducing it from the premises. As Tarski emphasized, formal proof in the modern sense results from refinement and “formalization” of traditional Aristotelian demonstration. Aristotle’s general theory of demonstration required a prior general theory of deduction presented in the Prior Analytics. His general immediate-deduction-chaining conception of deduction was meant to apply to all deductions. According to him, any deduction that is not immediately evident is an extended argumentation that involves a chaining of immediately evident steps that shows its final conclusion to follow logically from its premises. To illustrate his general theory of deduction, he presented an ingeniously simple and mathematically precise special case traditionally known as the categorical syllogistic. With reference only to propositions of the four so-called categorical forms, he painstakingly worked out exactly what those immediately evident deductive steps are and how they are chained. In his specialized theory, Aristotle explained how to deduce from a given categorical premise set, no matter how large, any categorical conclusion implied by the given set. He did not extend this treatment to non-categorical deductions, thus setting a program for future logicians.

Perspectives

This paper is a contribution to a re-examination of ancient logic from a modern perspective. Jan Lukasiewicz, the great Polish logician, teacher of Alfred Tarski and other logic giants, must be credited for founding this tradition and infusing it with a scholarly character that it still retains.

JOHN CORCORAN
University at Buffalo - The State University of New York

Read the Original

This page is a summary of: Aristotle's Demonstrative Logic, History and Philosophy of Logic, February 2009, Taylor & Francis,
DOI: 10.1080/01445340802228362.
You can read the full text:

Read

Resources

Contributors

The following have contributed to this page